Western Standard

The Shotgun Blog

« Randy Hillier: G20 crackdown reeks of tyranny | Main | WS Poll: Should there be an inquiry into the actions of police during G20? »

Monday, July 12, 2010

Run from the Rahn Curve

Recently, Shotgun blogger PUBLIUS featured a video made by the Center for Freedom and Prosperity concerning a graph of the so-called "Rahn curve". The video serves as a good example of what is wrong with the idea of founding upon quantitative economic arguments ones advocacy of individual freedom. And, given the political orientation of those telling us about the Rahn curve, an explanation of why libertarians are prone to making the aforementioned error is warranted.

In the comments section of the
 blog post about the Rahn Curve, I essentially 'promised' a video response. The argument below may be a bit more precise, but I did in fact prepare a video in which I opine extemporaneously upon the same subject discussed in this post. For those who would rather watch and listen than read, I include that video response below:
 


 There should be little argument that the Center's video is being presented by an organization that wants the world to view it as advocating individual freedom. Were that not the case, I sincerely doubt that the "Center for Freedom and Prosperity" would bother mentioning freedom, and would instead call itself something like "The Centre for National Prosperity" (a name that would be more fitting). In the video, the Center's spokesperson is Dan Mitchell, a libertarian economist who is both a founder of the Center, and is a senior fellow with the
Cato Institute. The Cato Institute takes its name from Cato's Letters, which the Institute describes as "...a series of libertarian pamphlets that helped lay the philosophical foundation for the American Revolution." The Cato Institute states that its mission is: "...to increase the understanding of public policies based on the principles of limited government, free markets, individual liberty, and peace."  In short, the video is presented by entities that wish to be regarded as advocates of individual freedom. 

The purpose of the video is informed by the fact that those providing the video wish to be regarded, in doing so, as advocates of individual freedom. Accordingly, the arguments set out in the video purport to be arguments in defence of individual freedom (hence, of capitalism).  So let us turn to the content of the video for the purposes of determining whether the video's message strengthens or undermines the case for individual freedom.  



The video gets off to a bad start. The "Rahn Curve" graph does not disclose what, exactly, is being plotted.  The X axis is labeled ambiguously as "Economic Performance", and the Y axis is labeled just as ambiguously: "Size of Government". That ambiguous labeling, together with such narrative as "But you the viewer only need to understand one thing", suggests that the producers of the video are not very concerned with having viewers actually understand the curve, so long as viewers accept the curve as economic proof that government is currently too big. With not too much googling, one can find for oneself the units that the Center thought should be replaced with ambiguous terms. Values on the X axis (which the Center labels "Economic Performance") are actually: Percentages of Annual Growth in GDP. Values on the Y axis are (which the Center calls "Size of Government") are: Percentages of Annual GDP that is Spent by Government". 

Mitchell tells the viewer that "economic performance" is maximized when government spending (a.k.a., the "size of government") is somewhere in the range of 15% to 25% of GDP. He goes on to deliver the video's take-home message: because U.S. government spending is in the 35% to 40% range, the Rahn curve demonstrates "...that government is too big, and this is reducing prosperity".

As an aside, I should add that, given that that which is spent by government must first also be taxed by government, it should not be surprising that the Rahn Curve has the same shape as the Laffer Curve. Yet the Rahn Curve is presented to the viewer as though it is a second piece of evidence that there is a right size for government.

There are numerous problems with the Center's use of the Rahn Curve as a basis for advocating individual freedom. First, consider the implications of an alleged freedom advocate advocating the maximization of annual growth in GDP. GDP growth is not a measure of the increase of any particular individual's productivity, but of the increase of the productivity of a collective entity: the country, or nation. Because the Center is advocating the maximization of GDP growth as a desired goal, it is implicitly advocating for the interests of a collective (the country, the nation), whether or not such a goal is in the interest of a particular individual.  In other words, the Center is necessarily advocating in favour of what utilitarians and other collectivists are prone to calling "the greater good" ("greater", as in: "of greater importance than the good of any one individual"). 

One cannot seriously expect to found the advocacy of individual freedom upon maximization of something that designed to serve "the greater good"; the good of the collective. When one uses the economic benefit of the greater good as the basis for arguing that individual freedom is desirable, one instantly undermines the cause of individual freedom. Every instance of individual freedom that leads to an economic result in which the collective does less well than it otherwise would have done but for the individual freedom serves as an argument against individual freedom. Does the use of marijuana, or alcohol, or opiates decrease growth in the collective productivity of the country? If so, then the result of alleged individual freedom advocates holding up collective productivity growth as a desired goal implies that some of the revenue spent by government should be used to force individuals not to use such substances. The violation of liberty is thereby held up as somehow being consistent with, or even necessary for, the defence of individual freedom.

Second, the assertion that there is an ideal size of government, together with the assumption that the size of government is properly measured by spending as a percentage of GDP, implies that it is ideal for the government to grow – more precisely, that it is ideal for government spending to grow -- as GDP grows. The Center for Freedom and Prosperity having as one of its aims greater productivity, the Center is, ironically, advocating the continuous growth of government (assuming the economy continues to grow). So, if one starts with the libertarian notion that "the best government is the government that governs least" (i.e., that smaller government is necessarily more compatible with individual freedom than is bigger government), one is left with the self-defeating spectacle of libertarians implicitly arguing for ever-growing government; a growth allegedly serving "the greater good". 

Worse, the Center provides us with not even an attempt to explain why productivity growth leads to a situation in which government needs more money. If one individual's efforts increase the productivity of the country, it does not follow that that productivity increase causes a state of affairs in which defending life, liberty, and property becomes more expensive. The notion that government spending should increase as a percentage of GDP is a welfare statist conception, founded upon the notion that so long as the percentage of wealth stolen from the public does not change, there is no harm done: the amount of wealth transferred from the increasingly productive to the under-productive or non-productive can increase as the economy grows. Such wealth redistribution, being accomplished by a gun pointed by government at the head of every producer, is neither an incentive for production nor consistent with the role of government in a free society: defending every individual's life, liberty, and property. 

Third, government spending is, itself, an ambiguous concept. There is simply no way that “government spending”
per se, is necessarily good or necessarily bad for productivity growth. Law enforcement is not, per se, good or bad for productivity. For example, the supposedly ideal 20% recommended in the video could be spent on defending every individual’s life, liberty and property. Trade requires that a person’s property not be obtained without his consent so, clearly, if government pays officers to ensure that nobody obtains another person’s property by such means as theft or fraud, productivity will be higher than were government to allow thefts and frauds to occur. But productivity will be undermined if government uses exactly the same amount of money to pay officers to force stores or factories to close on Sundays or religious holidays, or to seize the property of milk farmers who sell milk directly to consumers instead of complying with a law requiring them to buy quotas and sell their milk only to a milk marketing board. 

As another example, the government can spend $1.8M Canadian tax dollars to pay a year’s salary to approximately 6 Canadian judges who will try and convict murderers, rapists, and thieves. Alternatively, the government can spend that $1.8M Canadian tax dollars to buy a painting comprised of three vertical stripes ("
Voice of Fire"). The arrest and conviction of criminals will facilitate productivity and trade, but the purchase -- by a non-productive entity such as government - of three lines on a canvas, will not increase productivity. To the contrary, the government's purchase of the painting may well reduce productivity by taking money out of the hands of producers (i.e., taxpayers) who would have used the money as capital with which to facilitate more valuable production.

Fourth, in a political context, individual freedom means: not having ones life, liberty, or property taken without ones consent. Individual freedom is not a reference to government using force (i.e., laws, backed by guns) in an attempt to maximize the increase of the collective productivity of the country's inhabitants. Individual freedom is not a reference to government using force to increase tax revenues and government spending when the country's productivity increases. Individual freedom does not refer to government using force to redistribute wealth from those who produce it to those who do not. All such uses of force in the economy are instances of the very coercion from which the government is supposed to be
protecting individuals. They are instances of the very crimes for which the government rightly arrests and imprisons people. They are evidence that the government now regards itself as being above the law.
 
The whole notion of “smaller government”, similarly, has nothing
per se to do with individual freedom.  Individual freedom depends upon the quality of government, not the quantity of it. Individual freedom is not a function of how big or small a government is, per se, but of how effective government is in defending every individual’s life, liberty or property; how effective it is in ensuring that no person is deprived of his life, liberty or property without his consent. A small government that does not defend life, liberty and property is less desirable than a big government that limits itself to doing so. Therefore it makes no sense to assert that there is a given percentage of GDP that the government should take and spend (i.e., it makes no sense to advocate that there is a right size for government based upon economic figures). A government's expenditures will properly depend upon such things as how much crime there is; how many thieves, rapists, and murderers there are, et cetera. A largely moral and peaceful society with a given GDP will be much less expensive to govern than a largely immoral and violent one with the same GDP.

Now, if neither the alleged size of government nor the quantitative arguments of economics has anything to do with individual freedom, why do many libertarians spend so much time calling for “less government”?  Why do libertarians base so many of their arguments upon the attainment of economic goals? The answer to both questions is rooted in the fact that economics deals not with the qualities of things, but with the quantities of things; it deals explicitly not with right and wrong, but with more and less. And, because economics deals with quantities instead of with qualities, an economic argument gives libertarians a rallying cry to attract individuals whose qualitative opinions about government differ greatly, or are even in opposition. 

For example, quantitative economic arguments in support of “small government” allow libertarians to attract religious anti-abortionists who want to take away government’s ability to fund abortions, while also attracting anti-religious pro-choicers who want government to stop funding (or to stop providing tax breaks for) religions that oppose a woman’s right to choose to have an abortion. The result is a libertarian group that claims to advocate individual freedom though its members cannot agree about whether doctors who provide abortion services should be protected from those who bomb abortion clinics, or whether such doctors ought to be given the death penalty. 

The libertarian's conscious or unconscious attraction to economics is founded upon the hope that if you give people common quantitative conclusions with which they can agree, they will voluntarily stick their heads in the sand, or keep their mouths shut, with respect to the qualitative commitments that make their fellow libertarians their political enemies. And so we have libertarians who rally behind the anti-abortion Ron Paul, a proponent of Austrian economics, joining with libertarians who rallied behind - and continue to praise - pro-choice libertarians like Murray Rothbard who, similarly, was a proponent of Austrian economics. 

In discussing libertarians, I do not imply that I restrict my criticism - concerning the use of economics to justify individual freedom, or to bring people together despite their substantive opposition - to libertarians or members of Libertarian parties. The same misguided attraction to economics imperils other political parties. For example, in a recent
interview of blogger Andrew Lawton by Libertas Post, Lawton took the libertarian position that health care should be entirely privatized. Lawton is anti-abortion and he considers himself a "social conservative". Yet he told Libertas Post that "at the end of the day, I think the most important issues that we have to work on as conservatives are the issues that we agree on, which are economic issues". Like the big L libertarians, the big C conservatives attempt to use economics as a no-conflict zone between warring factions who somehow think it desirable, for electoral ends, to work together though their desired governmental ends are mutually exclusive. 

However, unlike libertarians and Libertarians, conservatives and Conservatives do not seek to be seen as advocates for individual freedom, and generally do not hold themselves out to be such. Accordingly, trying to unite people with economics does little to undermine the case for individual freedom when it is conservatives who engage in such folly. If anything, it undermines conservatism.

In contrast, when libertarians - holding themselves out to be proponents of individual freedom -- use economic arguments to bring together individuals who oppose one another on qualitative matters (e.g., anti-abortion vs. pro-choice), each instance of disagreement on such fundamental qualitative matters -- among alleged advocates of individual freedom -- serves to convince the public that "individual freedom" itself is itself an ambiguous concept; individual freedom itself is undermined.

The prospects for individual freedom would be undermined even more were libertarians -- having been drawn together by economic arguments -- somehow to win the reigns of governmental power. Returning to the abortion example, when conservatives disagree about abortion, and decide upon a "compromise" law in which women are free to have abortions in the first five months of pregnancy, but in which abortions conducted thereafter are punishable by imprisonment, the wisdom or insanity of the law is attributed to conservativism or to a Conservative party. 

In contrast, were a governing libertarian party -- a governing party that claims to be comprised of proponents of individual freedom -- to adopt the same 5-month law for abortions in order to accomplish the same comprise between its anti-abortionist and pro-choice membership, what would that tell the onlooking public? It would tell the public a range of falsehoods: that "individual freedom is not absolute"; that compromise is,
per se, a virtue, and is necessary; that "individual freedom is good in theory, but it doesn't work in practice"; that, ultimately, any argument in favour of individual freedom is flawed; that advocates of individual freedom are "naive" and should be ignored. In short, even were it possible to use economic arguments to unite de facto political opponents to win an election, the winning of the electoral battle would only serve to undermine the cause of individual freedom.

Nothing I have said about economics should be interpreted as a condemnation of economics itself. To the contrary, economics explains a great deal that should be known and that can help producers and consumers make wise choices. However, in a free society, economic choices are made by producers, who trade their respective values consensually. If the economic aim of a government is a free market, the government can ignore economic arguments altogether, and simply ensure that all trades a mutually consensual. Any other economic aim pursued by government (e.g., increasing government revenues and expenditures as the economy grows so as to maximize the productivity growth of the country), with or without economic knowledge, necessarily will involve using force to coerce individuals to part with their values non-consensually.

Accordingly, in a free society, economic arguments are of no use to government except for the identifying instances where an individual's life, liberty or property is being taken without his consent (e.g., arguments about the nature and effect of fractional reserve banking, monetary inflation, the use of gold as money, et cetera).  Any economic argument in favour of government having an economic aim other than a free market serves not to defend individual freedom, but to undermine it.

Posted by Paul McKeever on July 12, 2010 in Economic freedom, Libertarianism | Permalink

Comments

For whatever reason, the YouTube viewer appears, and the duration of the video is correctly displayed, but the play button will not work for me. If it is not working for you, you can watch the video by going directly to my youtube channel: http://www.youtube.com/paulmckeever

Posted by: Paul McKeever | 2010-07-12 8:06:20 PM


(The video works just fine for me, Paul).

I think you may have the level of abstraction wrong here. The point of the Rahn Curve is not undermined by their failure to specify exactly what that money is spent on. Like the Laffer Curve, it is supposed to be a broad generalization that leaves the specifics out of the equation.

That, too, applies to "small government." Of course that requires more to be said. But to say that you support "small government" is to say something sufficiently meaningful given the level of (appropriate) abstraction in a particular context. In a different context, to say you support "small government" would be a mistake.

It's nice to change the level of abstraction to make a philosophical point, but it's like telling someone who says "I like ice cream" that you have no idea what they're talking about because, after all, some things that count as "ice cream" will be disgusting and even the person who claims to like ice cream will agree is disgusting.

It's part of "getting" the implicature right, rather than focusing, anally, on the logical space of possibility.

Posted by: P.M. Jaworski | 2010-07-12 8:25:14 PM


Hi Peter:

That said, in terms of the Rahn curve, what do you regard as analogous to the ice cream, and what do you regard as analogous to the subset, disgusting ice cream.

Without that information, I initially offer these two responses.

1.Outside the space of possibility lies the space of impossibility. There is literally nothing to be gained from including the space of impossibility in any consideration or conclusion one may have. I not only focus on the possible, I entirely exclude the impossible, because the impossible is the irrational.

2. There is no rational abstraction founded upon an irrational premise. A demonstrably false conclusion, or an arbitrary conclusion, that is the logical result of the premises from which it is drawn, is proof positive that one or more of the premises is/are false or arbitrary (i.e., not in accord with the facts of reality for which, ultimately, there is physical evidence). So it is not as though, by condemning the validity/invalidity of an abstract concept, or the truth/falsity of a generalization, that one is saying something false about the concepts or percepts from which an abstraction or generalization was drawn. One does not rationally condemn ice cream if some of its flavours are praiseworthy and others of its flavours are yucky. In such cases, there's nothing false about saying you like ice cream and no reason to condemn its liking. But if all flavours of ice cream taste yucky, it is not an error to draw the conclusion "ice cream tastes yucky". The Rahn Curve smells yucky.

Posted by: Paul McKeever | 2010-07-13 5:24:35 AM


I'm not yet persuaded, Paul.

The Rahn Curve is useful, but there are a few buried and implicit premises.

One implicit premise is protection of private property. I believe it's explained in the video that the increase in productivity is partly a result of businesses altering their behaviour in ways including shifting their expenditure from protection/enforcement to research/marketing/etc.

Effective property rights enforcement is also implicit from the above. A business will only shift from protective activities to production-of-product activities on the condition that they believe they no longer have to protect/enforce any longer. That that task is taken over by the police & court system.

So the claim that it is consistent with the Rahn Curve that a government spend all its money on, say, ice cream, would be false.

That's one implicit claim in the Rahn Curve and in the explanation of the Rahn Curve.

It will be a matter of (some) controversy whether or not expenditure on infrastructure by the government promotes a move along the Rahn Curve toward greater productivity. Some will claim that private markets providing this will actually be more productive, others will insist that this is a task best left to the state.

At any rate, the Rahn Curve is not supposed to give us these details, just as the Laffer Curve is not supposed to. It is part of the implicature, and part of the longer explanation of the curves, which are included in the academic (or semi-academic, like in magazines) literature on the curves. No proponent of the Rahn Curve is so daft as to think how and what govs spend on, (or how or what govs tax for the Laffer Curve) is irrelevant.

Posted by: P.M. Jaworski | 2010-07-13 9:31:18 AM


Also, this claim is false: "There is no rational abstraction founded upon an irrational premise. A demonstrably false conclusion, or an arbitrary conclusion, that is the logical result of the premises from which it is drawn, is proof positive that one or more of the premises is/are false or arbitrary (i.e., not in accord with the facts of reality for which, ultimately, there is physical evidence)."

The truths of logic are not founded on any physical evidence. Same with the truths of mathematics.

Posted by: P.M. Jaworski | 2010-07-13 9:35:48 AM


I wrote: "There is no rational abstraction founded upon an irrational premise."

Peter replied:

"The truths of logic are not founded on any physical evidence. Same with the truths of mathematics."

That something is, formally, logical does not necessarily imply that it is rational. Consider the example I gave a year or three ago:

"All dogs write English literature.
Jake is a dog.
Therefore, Jake writes English literature."

We can rightly conclude that that conclusion is "rational", even if we can agree that something following the rules of a syllogism is "logical". The conclusion, in this example, is founded upon a false premise: that "All dogs write English literature". The false is the irrational. The conclusion "Jake writes English literature" is irrational, as a result of having been founded upon the irrational premise.

Hence Rand's principle objection to Kant, Hume etc., whose essential intellectual assaults were on man's ability to obtain the evidence necessary to ensure that the logical is the rational. Without evidence, we are left with the logic that a woman should be burned to determine whether or not she is a witch, because witches, like wood, float (after all - and I am here jesting - who can be certain that wood is not a witch, or that witches, wood, or even water, exist?).

Posted by: Paul McKeever | 2010-07-13 10:45:31 AM


Erratum: I am quite certain, mind you, that this:

"We can rightly conclude that that conclusion is "rational", even if we can agree that something following the rules of a syllogism is "logical". "

was meant to read:

We *cannot* rightly conclude that that conclusion is "rational", even if we can agree that something following the rules of a syllogism is "logical".

Posted by: Paul McKeever | 2010-07-13 10:47:29 AM



The comments to this entry are closed.